Po8
Blog: Ideals of 'physics foundations'
Date05 May 2010
CategoriesBlog

This is a blog article, which expresses informal views.

Contents

  1. Purpose of foundations
  2. Creative design process
  3. Borrowing from the scientific method
  4. Borrowing from philosophical reasoning
  5. The ideals:
    1. Traceability
    2. Explanation of physicality
    3. Hierarchical and vertically connected
    4. Quantitative
    5. Abstraction awareness
    6. Justified extensions
  6. Closing statement

What is the ideal foundational physical theory?

What are the essential features of a theory for the foundations of physics? What demands should a researcher or physicist make of a theory for it to be useful?

In answering these questions, we borrow some best-practice methods from the scientific method, philosophy and mathematics (proofs), and aspects of systems design from computer science.

Before we start, we should mention that although the word "theory" has specific meaning, we use it here in a very broad sense to cover hypotheses, ideas, schemes, models, or 'theories-proper'.

1. The purpose of foundations

As we've written elsewhere, the pursuit of good foundations is usually driven by a quest for knowledge, the prospect of new discoveries, and the desire to defeat a bizarre puzzle where the answers cannot found at the back of the book!

Simplicity

If we have good foundations for a subject area, then it's likely that we'll have a simple set of tools and rules that allows us to understand the body of the subject with little other supplemental material. Those rules are likely to apply throughout the subject. However, care should be taken not to use simplicity as an argument for the choice of theories, because that would be an aesthetic and subjective view, and ignore objective criteria.

Adjustments = not correct in the first place

If the emergent expressions of our foundations are not quite correct, we should learn from the exceptions to the theory. The temptation is then to refine the theory to match experimental results. While this is admirable, there are caveats.

A long-refined theory is likely to have missed some important foundations from the very beginning that are not as equally simple as the original elements of the theory.

Although we don't demand simplicity as a prerequisite to accepting a hypothesis, we do demand that exceptions to initially-simple foundations are justified, as having clearly categorised properties and relations to the foundations. Further, there should be verification that the additions are not a result of an epistemological mis-step, whereby a new type of entity is assumed to exist because it explains the difference between the simple model and the observation. The simpler answer in these cases, may be that the foundations are mismatched to the reality, and that better foundations would explain the behaviours with fewer additions to the ontology of the model. The better foundations would then detail the conditions required for the observed classical behaviours to emerge.

Easy to learn?

Complicated theories so are usually difficult to assimilate because of the twists and turns that must be mastered.

On the other hand, a revolutionary theory is likely to use new and simpler ideas, with more of the foundational terms being unified or equivalent in some way, but the down-side is that the ideas are likely to be incomprehensible to the majority - even those qualified to understand. Good theories often need re-interpreting to be understood by a wider readership.

Symmetry: a winning ingredient

In a unified theory, there are symmetries: aspects of a state that will not change under transformation, while other aspects do change. The ideal theory will be constructed almost entirely from similar symmetrical terms at a fundamental level, and these symmetries have implications for the whole subject, finding expression in the description of a reality, and having consequences at all scales.

2. Foundational physics as a creative design process

Theoretical physicists need to be creative to produce original ideas, a notion that is often missed by those who view science as a technical or engineering discipline.

What approaches are likely to succeed?

Researching new foundations requires deep knowledge and insight into the subject area, a very associative mindset (where many connections between many things are considered, even if most are rejected), and a diverse imagination that allows the physicist to see things differently, so that new ways can be found to create principles and structures that underpin the subject.

Persistence and determination also play a part, especially considering that a 'discovery' is the first successful communication of an given idea, and to be first, you have to have made more progress than your predecessors.

There is also a creative aspect to the way that scientists present their material to make it successful, either in their writing style, the approach and structure of their publications, the way they negotiate and communicate with like-minded researchers, and the infectious enthusiasm they generate when lecturing to colleagues or communicating with the public.

Creative Design: following a life cycle

On a more formal level, a theory or hypothesis is prepared in a process of creative design. There will be some objectives (otherwise there would be no project!), and some rules or design principles to follow during the creative process, to provide technical steering. As with the computer systems 'development life cycle':

  • A problem will be subjected to analysis,
  • Basic entities and actions will be isolated and the relationships between them identified,
  • Entities, processes, internal interfaces, and external interfaces will be coded (abstracted) in the simplest way possible,
  • A model is built to give the hypothesis some framework, context, and data,
  • The model is tested and reconciled with the reality that it purports to model.
  • Simulations are reviewed, debugged or re-written, and the cycle loops back for further refinements.

Eventually, a good theory will be released in a complete form, or it may be 'beta-tested' to allow others to test-drive it. Some theories are good enough that they are kept for proprietary advantage, or are (more responsibly) released for others to use.

Designs that meet analysed requirements

In the creative process, a designer may be presented with (or invent) options to resolve a requirement. For example, there might be a need to find a means for fields to change the position of a particle; there might be several ways that terms for fields to affect the relative states of conserved entities.

Choose carefully, or not at all

'Design decisions' will need to be made to choose between available options. Such design decisions are an intrinsic part of the creative process, and exploration of such options should be encouraged, so long as the designer is mindful of the need to converge the ideas with reality at some point, without 'losing the plot'. There should also be an awareness that choosing a perspective might colour or polarise any dependent ideas, and that an alternative choice is not necessarily the wrong one; dualities often present a choice of equally correct perspectives.

You don't need to choose

Having a choice could also be dangerous to a hypothesis. If design choices exist, it is unsatisfactory at best, and hiding a truth at worst, to choose one option arbitrarily from the landscape of possibilities only because it fits with reality or observation.

Instead, a choice must be informed from within, from more fundamental foundations. Choosing arbitrarily is making an assumption, and introducing inconsistency to a hypothesis. Fewer such assumptions make a strong hypothesis. Again, it's worth mentioning that choices might represent dualities (rather than 'correct' and 'incorrect'), where each choice is valid in its respective context. It must then be proved that both choices can work, that a relationship is established between the choices, and that all possible scenarios are covered by those choices.

3. Borrowing from the Scientific Method

We could easily quote some typical guidelines for paper submission, as they would of course apply here:

  • Reconcile with reality;
  • Make predictions;
  • Make new discoveries, providing novel material;
  • Draw relevant new connections;
  • Cite all sources so that fellows can check the background of work and identify original ideas;
  • Mark up all assumptions, so that potential weaknesses can be investigated;
  • Do good research (don't re-invent the wheel);
  • Use the concise language of the subject discipline; and
  • Provide (usually mathematical) tools for fellow scientists to use your work for themselves.

Applying some of these to the construction of a theory of foundational physics, a useful theory might do the following (non-exhaustive list):

  • Adequately describe or cite the background that an author assumes,
  • Provide plug-in tools that a reader can readily understand and use,
  • Indicate speculative passages with a measure of confidence,
  • Have a broad enough scope to be applied across many disciplines,
  • Provide new information by explaining more phenomena with simpler foundations,
  • Develop related fields (like mathematics),
  • Make predictions about phenomena that have not yet been proposed, measured nor observed.

4. Borrowing from philosophical reasoning

Philosophy and formal mathematics are both strict about the traceability of ideas, and notions of truth and proof. We should adopt the same rigour with all the entities, interfaces and processes that we design, by defining their origins and relationships with other phenomena, such that the whole body of work can be built from its lowest foundations to its highest hierarchical levels by the controlled introduction of separate principles and assumptions. The work then becomes traceable, and if an aspect of the work is found to be flawed or inadequate, the process of auditing, and then invalidating or refining the affected areas becomes relatively simple. If aspects were previously flagged as having low confidence, or have a mix of identifiable sound and unsound aspects, then these can provide clues about the shape of a more correct model, perhaps at a lower level.

If an aspect of the model is unexplainable, or cannot be justified other than by necessity, or cannot be described in relation to terms already described in the model, then it is a belief rather than a solid foundation. Beware justifying or qualifying a belief by accepting that it is only important within a limited scope of application, because that ignores exceptions that cannot be verified as truthy, and invalidates the model. Beliefs should be investigated further: is there an underlying foundation that can explain the existing model and its exceptions?

5. The ideals of a foundational theory for physics

Here goes...

  1. Traceability

    Ideas must relate to reality, and be reconcilable with experiment and observation (macro-extension). Ideas must also be reconcilable to proposed foundational principles (micro-extension). Understanding the scope and relations between phenomena will help identify incomplete mappings, a need for transformation or context, or enable new discoveries.

    Complete vertical traceability needn't be demonstrated in publications; it may just be a handy tool to help with the design process.

  2. Explanation of physicality

    There must be an explanation of how matter exists, rather than an assumption that it does exist. This means digging deeper than the notion of a physical entity like a particle or a wave, to speculate its components. It is healthy, rather than foolish, to endeavour to break a seemingly fundamental fermion (quark or lepton) or boson into smaller parts. These parts might not exist in the same way that we expect fermions to, and it takes some imagination to find a reasonable way that component states can exist 'behind the scenes' that may, in some circumstances, produce the phenomena that we currently recognise as fundamental (even if we can't observe them directly). This approach has produced revolutionary ideas throughout history.

  3. Hierarchical and vertically connected

    To help points 1 and 2, concepts and phenomena should be placed in a hierarchy. The levels should be states or expressions of the model, and steps between levels should be processes; both of which may have mathematical description. All levels must be implicit and self-generative from lower levels, without need of external ‘handle-turning’ processes.

  4. Quantitative

    For any given observation, it should then be possible to explain the epistemology of how the measurement becomes macroscopically quantifiable, and it should be possible to explain a traceable path from foundations, through the hierarchy of all the expressions and processes that contribute to the observation. This necessarily includes perspectives ('pictures') on the fundamental data, choosing appropriate limits in appropriate variables, understanding the linearity and complexity of a model, taking products and projections as appropriate to the model, and as a bonus should identify areas where information is discarded, mixed, or transformed by the mathematical or physical model. Most importantly, numeric predictions are testable, and the model can be evaluated on the accuracy of the predictions.

  5. Abstraction awareness

    The distinction should be made between (a) abstractions and (b) terms that are proposed to exist as entities or states. The transition to abstraction can then be seen as a point for further improvement (without precluding useful abstractions).

    Another aspect of abstraction awareness: if we think we are finished when our theory has no discrepancies with observation, we might merely be at the frontier of falsifiable knowledge, rather than have a true picture of reality. It is possible that our understanding is only 'sufficient' in the context of our observations, and that there are deeper truths to be uncovered.

  6. Justified extensions

    Where extra terms or phenomena are added, they must not be arbitrary, but must instead be explained in terms of the existing foundational terms. In other words, a new term must be either a new symmetry (that yields new discoveries in new expressions), or a new phenomena (which is described in terms of existing symmetries, and has other dual aspects or sibling terms).

Closing statement

Of course, we should never let formality get in the way of a good idea; a sketch on an envelope could generate as much excitement as an edition of a listed journal of peer-reviewed conference proceedings. The formality helps the communication of an idea, protects the assertion of the scientist as the work's author, is a form that is familiar and comfortable to digest, and with some editorial authority that it is 'good science'.

Admit errors, be keen to improve!

Beware the misguided individual who continues to evangelise poor work as good work, and who over-inflates the importance of their ideas: the 'crackpot physicist'. The problem with such cases is usually a lack of strength in depth of knowledge in physics (rather than a lack of formal education), and an inappropriate sense of associativity between physical phenomena. As in nearly all aspects of life, significant improvements can be made by listening to the advice of experts (if the author is lucky enough to receive it), admitting errors, acknowledging weaknesses, and being willing to revise or discard flawed aspects without being too precious about them.

Also beware people who censor ideas that they cannot understand, or who discredit ideas only because they devalue other areas of research (particularly their own). Such behaviour is not in the scientific interest, and it is the duty of physics (as a body of researchers) to be open to inspection and to be open to alternative ideas that have potential to improve the field. Breakthroughs in foundational physics are never convenient at the time they occur, but as years (and old creeds) pass, revolutionary ideas are developed into good theories or principles, and eventually become part of the curriculum.

The creative process

As mentioned above, 'marketing' can have a critical bearing on the success of an idea: poor presentation can cause a good idea to fail, and good presentation of a poor idea can mislead and waste time. Throughout the whole process – from conception and refinement of ideas, through to the style of their communication, collaborative developments, and the willingness to accept ideas – a creative process is at work.